It’s
time t0: the very first instant there is. At this instant, there exists God the Father
and God the Son. One event occurs at
this instant: God the Son is begotten of God the Father.
What
is the relationship between God the Father and God the Son? Well, we already have part of the story: the
latter is begotten of the former. Is
there anything else we can say at this point?
One might be tempted to conclude that we know also that they are
numerically distinct, since nothing is begotten of itself.
Certainly,
this claim of distinctness seems to fit well with some of the things God the
Son goes on to say. He says, after all,
that God the Father is greater than he is: and surely nothing is greater than
itself! Other things he says seem to at
least conversationally imply that he is distinct from God the Father, even if
they don’t logically entail it. He says,
for example, that no-one can come to the Father except through him (the Son): it
would be less misleading to simply say ‘No-one can come to me except through
me’ if that’s what this amounted to, as it surely would were the Father and the
Son the same being. All in all then, it
seems like there is good reason to conclude that we have two things here: the
Father and the Son.
Unfortunately,
the Son also says some things that suggest that he is not distinct from the Father.
He says that he and the Father are one.
He doesn’t elaborate too much on what he means (he has a fondness for the
cryptic!), but the smart money is on the claim that he’s saying they are of one
essence. And we have good metaphysical
reasons for thinking that if A and B are of one essence, they are numerically
identical. For surely it is part of the
essence of A that it is A and not
some other thing. And if B is not A then it is certainly not
part of B’s essence that it is A. So if
A and B are distinct then they are not
of one essence. We also have theological
reasons for thinking that the Father and the Son are identical, for we believe
each of (i) The Father is divine, (ii) The Son is divine, (iii) For all x, if x
is divine then x is a god, and (iv) There is exactly one god. And (i)-(iv) together entail that the Father
is the Son.
So we’re in a quandary: the story so far pulls in
two directions, some things indicating that the Father and the Son are
distinct, some things indicating that they are identical. Let us now see how the story progresses.
God the Father is really powerful. In fact, he can do anything metaphysically
possible. This is true at time t0,
and it remains true for ever. He never
loses any of his powers; and of course he never gains any, since he can already
do anything possible (and that’s as powerful as it’s possible to be). God the Son, on the other hand, starts off
life at t0 far less powerful.
(Hence his claim that the Father is greater than he is.) But unlike the Father, the Son grows in power
over time until, at the very last moment of time, tz, he is himself
capable of doing anything metaphysically possible. One of the things he can do at tz
is travel in time, this being metaphysically possible. And so he does: he travels back to t0,
at which point he calls himself God the Father and begets the earlier less
powerful version of himself, calling him God the Son.
This
is the story of a time-travelling deity.
At the beginning of time there is only God: but there are two ‘versions’
of him – there is the all powerful being he becomes
at the end of time, who travelled back in time to the first moment, and there
is the less powerful being that he started out as, who was begat by his more
powerful future self after he travelled back in time.
I
am not claiming that this is how the world is.
But I think it is possible, and that if it is true then the data we
started with is accounted for. Thus, I
think we have here a metaphysical model that vindicates the orthodox Christian
understanding of the relationship between God the Father and God the Son.
Consider
the first puzzle: how can the Son be the Father if the former was begotten of
the latter? Well, if time travel is
possible, cases of self-creation just aren’t that puzzling. Let’s suppose that a man undergoing a sex
change would be capable of giving birth.
So suppose I now, in 2012, travel back in time to 1979, wait a year and
get a sex change and then travel back in time to 1979 again; at that point my
male self that came back from 2012 can mate with my female self who came back
in time from 1980, who will then give birth to infant me in 1980, who will grow
up to back in time in 2012. This
scenario is perfectly consistent, and it involves me creating myself. So there’s nothing impossible about God going
back in time and begetting his earlier self.
It’s
also clear that if this is how things are, God the Son’s declaration that the
Father is greater than he is is a perfectly sensible thing to say. If I go back in time to 1980 then I can look
at infant Ross and truly say ‘He is me’, but I can also sensibly say ‘I am
taller than he is’. In general, if
something that changes across time travels back in time to a time when it was
different, then we can sensibly contrast how its later self is with how its
earlier self is, even though they are the same thing. Thus the Father, God’s later self, can
sensibly be said to be greater than the Son, his earlier self, despite them
being the same being.
Similarly,
if I go back in time to protect my infant self in the cradle, I can sensibly
say ‘Nobody gets to him except through me’.
And it’s simply not more
conversationally informative for me to say ‘Nobody gets to him except through
him’, despite the fact that I am
he. Since I can sensibly contrast my later
self with my earlier self – my later self is bigger and stronger – then I can
sensibly say that it is my later self protecting my earlier self and not my
earlier self protecting my earlier self, despite the fact that my later self is my earlier self. Likewise, if it requires a being like us in
some respects to bring us to a being who is so far beyond us in power, then the
Son can sensibly say that it is only he that can bring you to God the Father;
and it would not be better for him to say that it is only the Father that can
bring you the Father, despite the fact that he is the Father.
Note
that I’m not claiming that these contrastive claims are true, only that they are sensible claims to make in those
circumstances. Whether or not they are
true depends on some tricky issues concerning persistence and change. It’s a prima facie puzzle if A is F and
travels back in time to a moment when it is not F, for then it seems that at
that time A is F and not F – contradiction!
What should we say about this puzzle?
It’s obviously similar to the familiar problem of temporary intrinsics –
how can David be hairy at one time and not hairy at some other time (once he’s
lost his hair), given that it’s one
person here, and nothing differs from itself?
But in our case, it’s not another
time: it’s the same time, because the A that is F has gone back to meet the A
that is not F.
Here
are some common responses to the problem of temporary intrinsics. The perdurantist thinks that the thing that
is hairy is not David, but rather a temporal part of David, and the thing that
is not hairy is a different temporal part of David. Since these temporal parts are numerically
distinct, there is no puzzle in their being different in properties. When David says in his early life that he is hairy,
he speaks truly, because the truth-conditions of his utterance are that the
temporal part that makes the utterance is hairy. If this is the correct response to the
problem of temporary intrinsics, it carries over straightforwardly to the time
travel case. The later version of A that
travels back to meet its earlier self is really a different thing: it is a
later temporal part, and it is meeting its earlier temporal part, and so there
is no puzzle in one being F and the other not being so. On this view, I speak truly when I travel
back and say that I’m taller than my infant self: the temporal part that makes
that utterance is taller than the
temporal part that’s in the cradle.
Similarly, the Son speaks truly when he says that the Father is greater
than he is: the Father is God’s later temporal part, and does indeed have more
powers than the Son, who is God’s earlier temporal part.
But
suppose perdurantism is false. The two
most common endurantist solutions to the problem of temporary intrinsics need
modification if they are to handle the time travel case. On one view, things are incapable of changing
with respect to their monadic properties, and what we normally think of as a
thing changing with respect to a monadic property is in fact it standing in a
certain kind of relation to some times but not others: so while it looks like David
is hairy simpliciter at one time and not at another, in fact David is never hairy
or not hairy simpliciter but rather bears the being hairy relation to some time but fails to bear it to a later
time. But if we’re to allow for the time
travel case we will have to say that apparent monadic properties are not two
place relations between an enduring object and a time, but rather three place
relations between an enduring object, a time, and a place. So when A travels back to meet earlier A, it
is true simpliciter that A bears being F
to time t and place L1 and true simpliciter that it fails to bear that relation
to time t and place L2. (L1 being the
place the future version ends up at t, L2 being the place the earlier version
is at that time.)
What
are the truth-conditions for ‘A is taller than B at time t’ if height
properties are really three place relations between an object a time and a
place? There are various options:
perhaps it’s true iff every height relation A bears to some place at t is
greater than every height relation that B bears to some place at t; perhaps
it’s true iff there’s a mapping that takes you from the height relations A
bears to some place at t to the height relations B bears to some place at t
(leaving no relations out) and which maps greater relations onto lesser ones;
and there are other options. But if
either of those suggestions are correct, it would turn out to be false when I
go back in time and say, looking at my infant self, that I am taller than
he. For if A=B then they will bear the
same height relations to places at a given time, and so it’s hard to think of a
sensible option on which it could come out true that A is taller than B at a
time.
Another
common endurantist option is to hold on to the thought that apparent monadic
properties are just that, but to deny that such properties are ever had
simpliciter: instantiation of such properties is always relative to a
time. So David has being hairy a certain way (i.e. relative to the earlier time) but
he lacks that property some other way (relative to the later time). The natural extension of such a view to allow
for time-travel cases is to relativise instantiation to both time and
place. And it’s easy to see why, for
similar reasons to those above, this is going to lead to a similar conclusion:
that I won’t speak truly when I look at my infant self and say that I am taller
than he.
So
return to God the Son’s assertion that God the Father is greater than he
is. If God is a perduring object then there’s
no problem in this being straight-forwardly true. At t0 there are two distinct
things: the earlier temporal part of the spacetime worm that is God and the
later temporal part of God – the former lacks omnipotence, the latter has it,
and the utterance the former makes is thereby true. If God is an enduring object, however, it
looks like the Son’s utterance is false: for everything we can say about the
Son’s powers at t0 will also be things we can say about the Father’s
powers at t0.
I
don’t want to take a stand on the perdurantism versus endurantism debate
here. What I want to argue is that each
option adequately accounts for the data.
The perdurantist option does so by rendering the Son’s utterances
concerning his relationship to the Father straightforwardly true. The endurantist option renders some of them
false; but I think this shouldn’t worry us, because the Son’s claims are still
sensible things to say in these circumstances, and this is all we should need
to secure.
If
I’m an enduring object and travel back to meet my infant self, then I am in
1980 twice over: I am bi-located at that time.
Suppose I’m trying to locate my infant self, who is in a hospital in
Glasgow, but I don’t know how to get there from where my adult self is (Leeds,
let us suppose). You’re trying to help
me get there and you ask ‘Are you in Glasgow?’.
I can truly answer ‘yes’. I am in Glasgow, for I am in two places,
and one of them is in Glasgow. But while
true, it would be utterly unhelpful and disingenuous for me to answer in the
affirmative: my speaking thus would not help you help me in my plans to bring
my adult self to my infant self. And
while it would be false, it would nevertheless be completely helpful and
appropriate to say ‘No, I’m not in Glasgow, I’m in Leeds’. That’s false, because I’m both in Glasgow and in Leeds; but it’s a good thing to
say because it communicates to you the information that you want: that the
location I have in virtue of my adult self having travelled back to this time
is in Leeds, even though I also have a location in Glasgow in virtue of my also
having been an infant at this time. Likewise,
when I find my infant self and claim to be taller than he is, what I say is
strictly speaking false: everything true of him is true of me, for we are
identical, and so every height relation he bears to a place at this time (or
every way he has a height) is also a height relation I bear to a place at this
time (or is also a way I have a height).
Nonetheless, the false contrastive claim is a sensible thing to say and
can impart useful information: it tells you that the height I have in virtue of
having travelled back to this time as an adult is greater than the height I
have in virtue of having been born at this time.
God
the Son wasn’t speaking to metaphysicians, he was speaking to the folk. The data that needs to be recovered is that
he said something good: something that would impart good, true, information to
his listeners. Even given endurantism,
his utterance does this on the time-travel story, despite being strictly
speaking false. Everything you can say
about God the Son’s powers at t0 you can say about God the Father’s
powers at t0, since they are the same thing. Nonetheless, you learn something true and
useful from the Son’s utterance that the Father is greater than he is: you
learn that it is in virtue of this one being having come back in time after
having changed that he is omnipotent at that time, and in virtue of him having
begotten his earlier self at that time that he lacks omnipotence at that
time. The Son could have conveyed this
information with a literally true utterance if he had spoken in a more
metaphysically perspicuous manner; but since he was speaking to the folk and
not to a select audience of metaphysicians, it’s perfectly understandable why
he didn’t.
The
Son’s utterance that no-one can come to the Father except through him is
true. As would have been the utterance
that no-one can come to the Father except through the Father. But while both true – and while in some sense
they both say the same thing – the latter is not as good a thing to say as the
former. For the latter claim fails to
impart the vital information conveyed by the former: that it is virtue of God
having had his earlier properties that he is able to bring you to a being that
is so far beyond you, namely the all-powerful being he becomes. So it’s no surprise that the Son makes the
former pronouncement and not the latter: far from being less informative, it is in fact more so.
And so I think we have a model of the relationship
between the Father and the Son that adequately accounts for our initially
recalcitrant data. But what of the third
member of the Trinity, the Holy Spirit?
Well, it would be easy to account for the third member in just the same
way: have God travel in time twice.
Recall the story of me giving birth to myself: at the time I was born
there were three versions of me about (the father, the mother after I had a sex
change, and the child the first two versions of me gave birth to), because I
travelled back to that time twice as well as being born there. Thankfully, the Bible is pretty silent on the
relationship between the Holy Spirit and the Son and the Father, so you can fit
it in as you wish once you’ve got the general recipe.
Let me close by considering an objection. One might object at the very idea of God
starting out life as a limited being and only growing to be omnipotent over
time. That might be thought to violate
the claim that it is essential to
God’s very nature that he is omnipotent.
Care is needed here, however.
It’s perfectly compatible with the above account that God is essentially
omnipotent in that it is of his essence that he grow to become omnipotent. And God is
around and omnipotent right from the beginning of time, remember. He’s also around and limited at that time,
but he’s omnipotent at that time as well, because his later self travelled back
to then. And this might also be of God’s
essence: perhaps he has to so travel back (after all, if he didn’t travel back
to beget himself, where would he come from?).
And so it’s compatible with the proposed account that God is essentially
such as to become omnipotent, and that he is essentially such as to be
omnipotent at all times. What it’s not
compatible with is the claim that he’s essentially such as to be never not
omnipotent, since on this account he is sometimes both omnipotent and not
omnipotent. I doubt our intuitions
regarding God’s essence are so fine-grained that this is determinately what we
have in mind when he say that he is essentially omnipotent, so I’m unconcerned
about biting this bullet.
7 comments:
A couple of people have pointed me towards this paper by Brian Leftow:
"A Latin Trinity", Faith and Philosophy 21 (2004), 304-33. Reprinted in Michael Rea, ed., Oxford Studies in Philosophical Theology 1 (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009); Michael Rea and Thomas McCall, eds., Philosophical and Theological Essays on the Trinity (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009)
where apparently he appeals to time travel in giving a model of the Trinity. I haven't managed to get a hold of the paper yet, so I don't know how close what he says is to what I'm saying here, but I thought I should acknowledge it and point interested readers towards it!
Here's a link to the Leftow paper (this is the original F&P version): http://www.andrewmbailey.com/trinity/latintrinity.pdf
Another paper that's relevant is Harriet Baber's "Sabellianism Reconsidered" (Sophia, 2002). Link: http://andrewmbailey.com/trinity/sabellianism.pdf
I found your metaphysical model very interesting, and the metaphysics is, as is typical of you, very carefully done. I wonder about the theology though. In the version of the doctrine of the Trinity I favour, it's important that there are three tropes of personhood yet only one trope of divinity. This guarantees that the doctrine won't be tritheistic or modalist. It seems relatively clear to me that your model is not tritheistic (as it seems there is only one trope of divinity in your model), as it's relatively clear to me that Leftow's isn't either. But I wonder if it's not modalistic. Are there really three (including the Holy Spirit) tropes of personhood on your model? When a person travels back in time to visit her younger self, are there one or two tropes of personhood? It seems to me there's just one. But I could be wrong about that. I would be interested in your view. It's great to see you doing some philosophical theology.
I have serious theological worries (atemporality or at least immutability, simplicity, etc.), but I want to offer a constructive suggestion. The endurantist version relativizes to times and places (either by using relational properties or by using time-indexed monadic properties). But God is supposed to be either aspatial or omnipresent or in some sense both. Relativizing to times and places won't help the endurantist with an aspatial or omnipresent time-traveler, since on both views, wherever (if anywhere) one version is, there the other is, too.
I think that apart from your story, the endurantist would do better to relativize to internal times, as that would account for time-travel of ghostly beings that can interpenetrate (and hence can time travel to the past and "twice over" be in exactly the same place, but "with different properties"), and that would solve this problem. (Not for those of us who believe God is atemporal.)
Andrew: thanks!
David: no, I agree, there's strictly speaking only one person on this view (although it might be appropriate to say sometimes that there are 3). So yeah, I can see why you might rule it out on those grounds. I was thinking: something's gotta go if you're aiming to give an account of the Trinity, so the strict truth of 'there are three persons' is mine. (I'd rather give that up than 'there is one God'!)
Alexander: very interesting, thanks!
Thanks, Ross. That's really helpful. I think you're right that something's gotta go. I think the choice is amongst these three:
There's one trope of divinity.
There are three tropes of personhood.
The identity relation is absolute, that is, not relative to a sortal.
Because of my theological commitments, I give up absolute identity in favour of relative identity. Relative identity is very helpful in solving a lot of theological problems, not least giving a coherent doctrine of the Trinity that respects what I take to be theological constraints. (Assuming of course that relative identity itself is coherent . . .)
:時間的計算單位,通常以10分鐘或15分鐘算一節。 (現主流以10分鐘為1節,1小時為6節)
△訪檯:公關原在A包廂服務,暫借3~10酒店公關分鐘不等,到B包廂向其他客人打聲招呼,之後再回原A包廂。
△跑檯:兩桌以上客人同時坐同一位公關(目前都會區的酒店較少)。
△點檯:指定某位公關(一般以多加2節or3節計算)。
△卡檯:排換其他公關。
△看檯:公關到包廂內讓客人選擇。
△止檯:等同於卡檯。
△轉檯:公關從正在服務的A包廂,酒店賺錢轉往另一間B包廂。
△冰檯:如某公關時常無法配合公司合理政策(工作態度不佳),導致業績幹部或大班,不想也不敢帶上檯(怕因此流失客人)。
△打槍:行政人員帶公關讓客人挑選,而客人拒絕,但再排換其他公關。
△快歌:指公關在包廂內點快節奏的歌曲來炒熱氣氛。
△框:買時段到底的意思,一般以7小時計算(12點以前買到6點,12點後買到7點,2點過後最少買足4小時等等)至於"框"這段時間內,可以在店家包廂繼續唱歌或外出陪客人吃飯,看電影...等等。
△解框:除非客人要有充分理由,酒店應徵才可讓店家解除原本【框】的消費,以保障公關權益。
△大框:買足公關一整天的節數,一般以10小時計算(可不用進店家打卡報班)。
△全場:等同於大框的意思。
△打卡框:也算是大框全場的一種,不同的是必須
Post a Comment